A relation $R\colon A\mathrel {\rightarrow \kern -9.5pt\mathrlap {|}\kern 6pt}B$ from $A$ to $B$1,2 is equivalently:
Let $A$ and $B$ be sets.
A relation $R\colon A\mathrel {\rightarrow \kern -9.5pt\mathrlap {|}\kern 6pt}B$ from $A$ to $B$1,2 is equivalently:
A subset $R$ of $A\times B$.
A function from $A\times B$ to $\{ \mathsf{true},\mathsf{false}\} $.
A function from $A$ to $\mathcal{P}(B)$.
A function from $B$ to $\mathcal{P}(A)$.
A cocontinuous morphism of posets from $(\mathcal{P}(A),\subset )$ to $(\mathcal{P}(B),\subset )$.
A continuous morphism of posets from $(\mathcal{P}(B),\supset )$ to $(\mathcal{P}(A),\supset )$.
(We will prove that Item 1, Item 2, Item 3, Item 4, Item 5, and Item 6 are indeed equivalent in a bit.)
We may think of a relation $R\colon A\mathrel {\rightarrow \kern -9.5pt\mathrlap {|}\kern 6pt}B$ as a function from $A$ to $B$ that is multivalued, assigning to each element $a$ in $A$ a set $R(a)$ of elements of $B$, thought of as the set of values of $R$ at $a$.
Note that this includes also the possibility of $R$ having no value at all on a given $a\in A$ when $R(a)=\text{Ø}$.
Another way of stating the equivalence between Item 1, Item 2, Item 3, Item 4, and Item 5 of Definition 8.1.1.1.1 is by saying that we have bijections of sets
natural in $A,B\in \operatorname {\mathrm{Obj}}(\mathsf{Sets})$, where $\mathcal{P}(A)$ and $\mathcal{P}(B)$ are endowed with the poset structure given by inclusion.
We claim that Item 1, Item 2, Item 3, Item 4, and Item 5 are indeed equivalent:
Item 1$\iff $Item 2: This is a special case of Chapter 4: Constructions With Sets, Item 2 and Item 3 of Proposition 4.5.1.1.4.
Item 2$\iff $Item 3: This follows from the bijections
where the last bijection is from Chapter 4: Constructions With Sets, Item 2 and Item 3 of Proposition 4.5.1.1.4.
Item 2$\iff $Item 4: This follows from the bijections
where again the last bijection is from Chapter 4: Constructions With Sets, Item 2 and Item 3 of Proposition 4.5.1.1.4.
Item 2$\iff $Item 5: This follows from the universal property of the powerset $\mathcal{P}(X)$ of a set $X$ as the free cocompletion of $X$ via the characteristic embedding
of $X$ into $\mathcal{P}(X)$, as in Chapter 4: Constructions With Sets, Proposition 4.4.5.1.1. In particular, the bijection
is given by extending each $f\colon A\to \mathcal{P}(B)$ in $\mathsf{Sets}(A,\mathcal{P}(B))$ from $A$ to all of $\mathcal{P}(A)$ by taking its left Kan extension along $\chi _{X}$, recovering the direct image function $f_{!}\colon \mathcal{P}(A)\to \mathcal{P}(B)$ of $f$ of Chapter 4: Constructions With Sets, Definition 4.6.1.1.1.
This finishes the proof.
Let $A$ and $B$ be sets and let $R\colon \mathrel {\rightarrow \kern -9.5pt\mathrlap {|}\kern 6pt}B$ be a relation from $A$ to $B$.
We write $\mathrm{Rel}(A,B)$ for the set of relations from $A$ to $B$.
We write $\mathbf{Rel}(A,B)$ for the sub-poset of $(\mathcal{P}(A\times B),\subset )$ spanned by the relations from $A$ to $B$.
Given $a\in A$ and $b\in B$, we write $a\sim _{R}b$ to mean $(a,b)\in R$.
When viewing $R$ as a function
we write $R^{b}_{a}$ for the value of $R$ at $(a,b)$.1
Let $A$ and $B$ be sets and let $R,S\colon A\mathrel {\rightarrow \kern -9.5pt\mathrlap {|}\kern 6pt}B$ be relations.
End Formula for the Set of Inclusions of Relations. We have
Since we have $\operatorname {\mathrm{Hom}}_{\{ \mathsf{t},\mathsf{f}\} }(R^{b}_{a},S^{b}_{a})=\left\{ \mathsf{true}\right\} \cong \mathrm{pt}$ exactly when $R^{b}_{a}=\mathsf{false}$ or $R^{b}_{a}=S^{b}_{a}=\mathsf{true}$, we get
On the left hand-side, we have
Since $(a\sim _{R}b\implies a\sim _{S}b)$ iff $R\subset S$, the two sets above are isomorphic. This finishes the proof.